SUMMARY:
... "Aequitas canonica" (Canonical equity) is used as a label to characterize the essence of
canon law since the Middle Ages. ... This passage can prove that
equity is seen here in opposition to indulgence and mercy.
... In a decretal of Pope Eugenius III, we can already see aequitas as a
canonical concept that could be substituted for misericordia or moderation as
being the antithesis to rigorism in the interpretation of the canons. ... The
replacement of misericordia (mercy) by aequitas (equity) can be seen as the consequence of a
more jurisprudential understanding of canon law in the teaching of Stephen of
Tournai (1170); but the old tradition of misericordia does not totally disappear in
this development of doctrine, because Stephen saw aequitas in canon law as
enforcing minor penalties or tolerating sinners in clerical office. So aequitas had the function of Ivo
of Chartres's (ca. 1100) misericordia also in Stephen's idea of
canon law. ... There was no difference between authors of civil law and canon
law declining to apply a concept of aequitas non scripta (Non-written equity) within
the legal system. ... "Rigor iuris" without aequitas was for Hostiensis
(† 1270) nothing but "excessus iuris'. ... I only want to mention that one of the
greatest postglossators, Baldus († 1400), accepted the idea that aequitas canonica
distinguished canon law from civil law and also transformed
some legal rules of civil law. ...
[*95]
"Aequitas canonica' is used as a label to characterize the essence of canon
law since the Middle Ages. The code of canon law which was promulgated in 1983
provides a general rule to be applied in all cases where special statutes do
not exist. The official English translation of Canon 19 states that: "Unless
it is a penal matter, if an express prescription of universal or particular
law or a custom is lacking in some particular matter, the case is to be
decided in light of laws passed in similar circumstances, the general
principles of law observed with canonical
equity, the
jurisprudence and practices of the Roman Curia, and the common and constant
opinion of learned persons." n1
In nearly two thousand years the history of canon law,
the concept of equity was not always used to describe
canon law as distinct from other legal systems. But the term "aequitas' is
already applied in late antiquity by Latin church fathers to describe the
Christian ideal of justice, justice that would include
not only a measure of equality and proportionality as in the Aristotelian
tradition, but which would also include charity and indulgence in special
cases. The element of charity as a component of perfect justice
is already mentioned by St. Augustine in one of his letters. n2 However, it is
difficult to find in late antiquity any idea which takes the canons as special
rules of equity being by that quality distinct from
the leges. On the other hand, the concept of equity is
often used to characterize and legitimize the legislation of the Christian
emperors so that their legislation is seen a special quality. n3
Equity, as a concept, is the creative element for the development
of law. n4 This is based on a Ciceronian idea n5 which the emperors used to
justify the changes of law already prior to the time of conversion to
Christianity so by Antoninus Pius: "Etsi nihil facile mutandum est ex
solemnibus, tamen ubi aequitas evidens poscit, subveniendum est." n6 (Though
changes in solemn form are not easily admitted, yet, where aequitas de [*96]
mands it, help should be granted.) This famous formulation by the emperor was
later used by Justinian for one of the regulae iuris of the Digest. n7 But let
us repeat that "aequitas' was not known within the church of the late Roman
Empire to give to the canons a higher dignity in comparison to the laws; it
was not regarded to be a special quality of positive canon law.
In the early Middle Ages, equity was identified with
justice in its meaning and seen in opposition to all
sorts of moderation, indulgence and commiseration as singular deviations from
justice. "Aequitas' simply meant perfect
justice. We can see this use of the term of aequitas in a famous
passage of the Sententiae by Isidore of Seville, where we read the following
sentence: "Omnis qui recte iudicat, stateram in manu gestat, et in utroque
penso iustitiam et misericordiam portat; sed per iustitiam reddit peccatis
sententiam, per misericordiam peccantis temperat penam, ut iusto libramine
quaedam per aequitatem corrigat, quaedam vero per miserationem indulgeat."
(Everybody judging righteously, has to keep a pair of scales in his hand to
give the same weight to justice and commiseration; but
by justice he pronounces the sentence for
transgressions, by mercy he moderates the penalty, so that something is
corrected by equity according to the right standard,
but something is forborne with commiseration). n8 This passage can prove that
equity is seen here in opposition to indulgence and
commiseration. Equity was a measure for the judge to
determine the appropriate penalty, which should not be tempered by
commiseration. This Isidorian sentence is formulated in a context to describe
the duty of all kinds of judges, not referring specifically to judicial
decisions by the church, but it was taken over by the famous collector Bishop
Burchard of Worms in his Decretum in the beginning of the 11th century in the
section collecting the major rules of procedural law in the church (Book 16);
n9 later the same text was included in Gratian's Decretum (Dist. 45, c.10)
- the authoritative textbook of classical canon law. "Aequitas' and "Misericordia'
are still contrary to each other in these definitions transmitted by the
canonical collections.
At the end of the eleventh century, Bishop Ivo of Chartres gave a very
important outline of the methods of canon law and of the character of its
rules - the canons - in his famous prologue to his canonical collections. In
this great document, a doctrine of interpretation for canonical rules is
developed in which we find the concept of "regnum charitatis' as the [*97]
most important goal for all application of canon law. Canonical rules should
be understood "secundum rigorem, secundum moderationem, secundum judicium,
secundum misericordiam" n10 - but aequitas is not mentioned here as a
principle of interpretation.
I cannot give an outline of the importance of the concept of aequitas during
the 12th century in the major works of legistic literature inside and outside
Bologna. Modern research in medieval legistic literature can refer the origin
of the famous paroemia, "Nihil enim aliud est equitas quam deus," to the
Exordiam institutionum, a juristic introduction to Justinians' Institutes
written by the glossator Martinus in the first half of the 12th century. In
the same work, aequitas is called "iusticie fons et origo." n11 Martinus also
provides a second definition of aequitas: "equitas est rerum convenientia que
in paribus causis paria iura desiderat." n12 These Martinian definitions were
used in a number of works by the earliest school of Roman law in Southern
France: the Summa Institutionum "Iustiniani est in hoc opere', the "Exceptiones
Petri', the "Quaestiones de iuris subtilitatibus' and the Summa Trecensis. n13
Martinus also gave to every judge the right to interpret the law according to
equity and to apply not only "equitas constituta in
legibus' but also "equitas rudis' - principles of justice
not embodied in positive law - in the decision of cases. n14 [*98]
In Gratian's Decretum, compiled around 1140, we do not find aequitas as the
guiding principle of interpretation as we have it in the Roman law school of
Martinus. Magister Gratian refers to misericordia and indulgentia as
principles of interpretation, but usually does not relate these canonical
concepts to aequitas. In his Dicta, the term "aequitas' is used only four
times.
When Gratian alludes to the sentence of Christ in the case of the
adulterous woman in the Gospel of St. John 8.7, he refers to Christ's decision
as "equitatis sententia'. n15 I think that aequitas is seen here to be the
highest form of justice. On two other occasions,
Gratian uses the term of aequitas in dealing with the problem of granting
individual special rights to churches, monasteries and persons in the form of
privileges. The Roman church, which is according to Gratian explicitly not
bound by the canons as general rules, can always grant privileges, but these
privileges should be given "considerata rationis equitate', and he defines
aequitas as "mater iusticiae'. n16 The definition of equitas as "mater
iustitiae' comes very near to the Martinian definition of "fons et origo
iuris' - in connecting aequitas with ratio in the formulation "rationis
equitate'. Gratian seems to refer to a guiding principle that would prevent
arbitrariness in the granting of privileges, something near to Martinus'
definition "paria iura in paribus causis.' "Rationis equitate' may be an
original concept found by Gratian, but it also comes near to Martinus'
formulation and may have been influenced by this school of Bolognese
glossators. Canonical jurisprudence of
equity
Gratian never used "aequitas' to describe a distinctive quality of canon law
in comparison to civil law. But this very concept was used by Pope Eugenius
III in a decretal letter written ... about 1150 to a famous canonist, Magister
Omnebene, who acted as papal judge delegate in an ecclesiastical law suit. n17
Omnebene asked the Pope whether he should require the oath of calumny from the
parties of that lawsuit. According to a procedural rule put into force by
Emperor Henry III, and later repeated by Pope Honorius II, the oath of calumny
should be avoided by [*99] clerics and not enforced on them in lawsuits.
Eugenius III, by referring to this imperial law as a rule of canon law,
ignores totally the rule's legislative origin. At the same time he gives as an
"obiter dictum' the rule that ecclesiastical lawsuits should find their end
"non ex legum districtione, sed ex canonum equitate.' As far as I can see,
this is the first source which attributes to canon law a higher dignity of
aequitas in comparison to the "districtio legum'. The Roman curia had, at that
time, already a high meaning of its developing legal order soon is transformed
by the case law of papal decretals. In this decretal of Eugenius III, we can
already see aequitas as a canonical concept that could be substituted for
misericordia or moderation as being the antithesis to rigorism in the
interpretation of the canons. This idea of aequitas is later found in the
Summa of Stephen of Tournai, who was a French canonist trained in Bologna,
writing the Summa after his return to France in 1166, he was one of the first
authors of a French school of canon law. In the prologue to the Summa, Stephen
taught that contradictions between canonical rules could be understood because
some canons were given ex rigore, while other canons ex dispensatione vel
equitate. n18 Aequitas is now used to describe the qualities of parts of the
written law of the church and the dichotomy rigor - aequitas takes the place
of the older conceptual division of rigor - misericordia. The replacement of
misericordia by aequitas can be seen as the consequence of a more legalistic
understanding of canon law in the teaching of Stephen of Tournai; but the old
tradition of misericordia does not totally disappear in this development of
doctrine, because Stephen is seeing aequitas in canons enforcing minor
penalties or tolerating sinners in clerical office. So aequitas has the
function of Ivo's misericordia also in Stephen's idea of canon law. Stephen
also frequently used the concept of equity in his
letters which give us an impression of his activity in legal practice. He
established aequitas canonica "as a juridical principle in the church's law
and worked from a coherent notion of it." n19
Aequitas as the most characteristic quality of canon law finds an impressive
distinction in the Summa Coloniensis, the work of a French or German canonist
who wrote a summa on the Decretum in Cologne in about 1169. The author
distinguishes different grades of equity in canon
[*100] law: 1)aequitas summa - the law of major sacraments like baptism and
the eucharist; 2)aequitas secunda - the law of ecclesiastical orders;
3)aequitas tertia - the law of marriage; 4)aequitas quarta - the law of church
property. n20 The term of aequitas is used to describe a hierarchy of norms
taking its points of reference from an understanding of the sacraments.
Equity is also used to distinguish a fundamental law, the
constitution of the church, from the layers of law open to legislative changes
and individual dispensation. However, this concept of a hierarchy of norms was
never brought into a system by legislation like that of modern states with a
constitution - the Catholic church did not accept the idea of a lex
fundamentalis being equivalent to the constitution of a state. According to
Stephen of Tournai, it belonged to the office of the pope to decide about the
degree of equity to be included into the law of the
church. Stephen wrote in one of his letters to Pope Clement III (1187-1191),
using a quotation from the Justinian Code: "Interpretationem inter ius et
equitatem positam vobis solis et oportet et licet inspicere." n21 So in the
12th century aequitas, without any differentiation, could continuously be used
for interpretation of the ancient and modern law of the church.
Since the time of Pope Alexander III (1159-1181), Papal decretals had made use
of aequitas especially for procedural law. Canon law had inherited from Roman
law a precise body of rules in procedural law that was systematically arranged
in the literature of ordines iudiciorum and iudiciarii since the 12th century.
Papal decretal legislation changed some of these rules, for instance, the
calumny oath, but it never came near to a total revision of that Roman law
heritage. On the other hand, flexibility was needed for the activity of the
numerous judges delegate who acted with papal authority, but were without a
possibility to ask for advice in every detail. In this situation, aequitas
could be used as a general principle to give judges practical independence
without breaking obedience to the letter of the law. So Alexander III
instructed the archbishop of York to admit all kinds of rational exceptions in
a law suit without being restricted by any enumeration of exceptions in the
written law. n22 This possibility to deviate from strict formality in
procedure is grounded in "iuris aequitas' according to the pope. The principle
of aequitas was also used by Pope Innocent III in 1202 to justify the possi
[*101] bility of switching to a possessory action from a petitory action at
any stage of a law suit. n23 Despite its contradiction to the rules of Roman
law - here aequitas is obviously used as motivating and justifying papal
legislation.
This application of aequitas as a motive for legislation and legal change is
one of its most important uses in the medieval world. Whereas in late
antiquity the emperor is entitled to employ aequitas in legislative acts, the
pope now takes the emperor's place in this function even with the claim to
revise secular law as a subsidiary legislator. This papal right was used
primarily to change procedural rules of Roman law. Roman law had developed the
extraordinary remedy of "restitutio in integrum', together with the rule of
stopping any action of the judge after initiating the procedure of restitutio
- "in integrum restitutione postulata ne quid novi fiat." n24 Innocent III
changed this rule for the case of suspicion of chicanery by the party asking
for restitution if the defendant would give security for the eventuality of
losing the lawsuit. n25 This change in law was justified by the pope as "aequitate
pensata'. The most interesting decretal in the field of equity,
however, came from Pope Honorius III in 1218. This pope had to deal with the
practice of ecclesiastical jurisdiction in the conquered territories of the
Byzantine Empire. He wrote to his legate that canon law could be applied among
the Greeks in a moderate way, taking into account the frequency of
transgressions by Latins and Greeks, but he added that the law had to be
followed without exceptions in sacramental matters like marriage law. n26 In
all cases without rules of written law, the papal representative should act
according to aequitas "in humaniorem partem.' Aequitas then became a principle
to decide all cases not foreseen in the existing body of law. This gave
special freedom to the judge in these remote areas. It also identified
aequitas by papal authority with a practice defined as "humanior', a response
to human needs.
Let us summarise the role of aequitas as it was used in papal decretal law
between 1140 and 1234 - prior to Gregory's IX' comprehensive legislation in
the Liber Extra. Aequitas is mentioned:
1. As a means of interpretation of canonical rules in the direction of
moderation and commiseration. Canon law had brought these concepts as new
substantive elements to the concept of equity as it
had been tradi [*102] tionally understood in Roman law. This identification
of originally separated elements was mainly worked out by Stephen of Tournai.
2. As a concept to modify rules of strict law in the direction of free
judicial discretion. This use of equity could lead to
a substantive modification of procedural rules.
3. As a principle to fill the gap in a legal system that did not know a
codification, and relied more on written common law than on regional customary
law. So aequitas was used as something like a general clause, as in the case
of restitutio in integrum.
4. As a justification for legal change and new legislation. It legitimized
developments in law and removed long lasting legal traditions.
Aequitas in canon law was, therefore, a necessary conceptual instrument for
the professor in the classroom, for the professional judge in the church
courts and for the papal legislator in the Roman curia.
Hostiensis
This concept of equity in canon law was not always
fully accepted by the doctrine of the canonists of the 12th and 13th
centuries. The jurisprudence of the canonists was not only guided by the text
of the decretals, but also influenced by the model of civil law doctrine. In
the field of aequitas, the Bologna civil law school removed the tendency of
Martinus and installed a doctrine that would only accept aequitas scripta as a
guideline for judicial decision. Aequitas could therefore not serve as a
general device for free judicial decision. This careful restriction of the
role of aequitas in law was also accepted by the most important canonist at
the end of the 12th century, Huguccio of Pisa. n27 Aequitas non scripta could,
according to him, only be used for gaps in positive law. This prevailing
opinion among the canonists, similar to the civilians, was for instance,
formulated by Bernardus Parmensis in the Glossa Ordinaria to the Decretals of
Gregory IX. "Ius semper est praeferendum equitati ... Hic (= X 1.36.11) de
aequitate non scripta quae tunc tantum servanda est cum ius deficit." n28
There was no difference between authors of civil law and canon law declining
to apply a concept of aequitas non scripta or cerebrina within the legal
system.
Canon law, however, gave another definition of aequitas scripta than the
authors of Roman law. The association of aequitas with the special canonical
concept of misericordia was upheld by the prevailing tradition among the
canonists. Johannes Teutonicus, the author of the Glossa Ordinaria to
Gratian's Decretum, wrote that without any excep [*103] tion "potius debet
iudex sequi misericordiam quam rigorem" n29 - the judge should follow
principles of commiseration more than those of strict interpretation of law.
The main idea of defining equity in canon law was
fully developed by the greatest author of canon law in the 13th century,
Cardinal Henricus of Segusio, or Cardinalis Hostiensis. Hostiensis gave three
definitions of aequitas in his opus maagnum, the Summa Aurea:
1. First he defined aequitas as a synthesis of justice
and commiseration: "Aequitas est iustitia dulcore
misericordiae temperata" - aequitas is a principle for exceptional situations,
but an everywhere pervading element of justice in
canon law.
2. "Aequitas vero est media inter rigorem et dispensationem sive misericordiam"
- aequitas is not simply identified with misericordia but in the middle
between rigorous application of canonical rules and a benign deviance from
strict application.
3. "Aequitas est modus rationabilis, regens sententiam et rigorem, haec enim
est aequitas, quam iudex, qui minister iuris est, semper debet habere pro
oculis." Aequitas is a rational use of legal rules, and excludes all kinds of
arbitrary jurisprudence in the practice of ecclesiastical courts. "Rigor iuris'
without aequitas was for Hostiensis nothing but "excessus iuris'. n30
Additionally, Hostiensis gave another argument for the supreme role of equitas
in canon law. The principles of aequitas had to be applied to avoid any danger
to Christian souls - the "periculum animarum'. n31 By that reason canonistic
scholarship could explain and justify for instance, the change in the law of
prescription requiring uninterrupted good faith. This new rule was regarded as
equitable because it avoided bad conscience for the person favored by those
rules. In fact, canon law was a legal system created to foster spiritual
welfare and therefore, it had to be dominated especially by equity
principles.
The influence of canonistic theories of aequitas canonica on the civilians of
the 14th century may not be discussed in this paper. I only want to mention
that one of the greatest postglossators, Baldus, accepted the idea that
aequitas canonica distinguished canon law in its quality from civil law and
could also transform some legal rules of civil law. In [*104] the question
of prescription, civil law should accept according to Baldus, the requirement
of uninterrupted good faith. Until then this doctrine had not found acceptance
in the secular courts. Baldus wrote about this canonical rule: "de facto non
servetur, sed cum sit aequum et salutare debet servari." n32 The concept of
aequitas canonica distinguished Canon law as a legal system from Roman law,
but found its expression in some rules which were integrated into the ius
commune applied by secular as well as ecclesiastical courts. This historical
development between the 12th and the 14th centuries gave to the ius commune a
socioethical foundation which is still alive in the legal heritage of Europe.
FOOTNOTES:
n1. Code of Canon Law 9 (Latin-English ed. 1983).
n2. Augustine Ep. 153, 26 (CSEL 44) 426: "Iustitiam quippe et nemo male habet
et, qui non dilexerit, non habet."
n3. See Pringsheim, Romische Aequitas des chrislichen Kaisers, Acta Congressus
Iuridici I 120-152 (1935).
n4. Berger, Art. Aequitas, Encyclopedic Dictionary of Roman Law (Transactions
of the American Philosophical Society, N.S. vol. 43/2, col. 354 1953).
n5. Cicero, Topica II 9 (H. Bornecque ed., Ciceron, Divisions de l'art
oratoire. Topiques), p. 69f: "Ius civile est aequitas constituta, eis, qui
eiusdem civitatis sunt, ad res suas obtinendas; eius autem aequitatis utilis
est cognitio; utilis est ergo iuris civilis scientia."
n6. Dig. 4.1.7 pr.
n7. Dig. 50.17.183: "Etsi nihil facile mutandum est ex sollemnibus, tamen ubi
aequitas evidens poscit, subveniendum est."
n8. Isidorus Hispalensis, Sententiarum Lib. III, c.52 (P.L. vol. 83, col.
721).
n9. Burchard, Decretum 16.25 (P.L. vol. 140, col. 913).
n10. Ivo Carnotensis, Prologus (P.L. vol. 161, col. 47). For Ivo's ideas see
my article "Ivo von Chartres', TRE XVI 422-427 (1987).
n11. See Fitting, Juristische Schriften des fruhen Mittelalters 216. Other
edition in I Palmieri, Scripta Anecdota Glossatorum 4 (2nd ed. 1914). For the
Exordium Institutionum or Materia by Martinus see Kantorowicz, Studies in the
Glossators of the Roman Law 53 and 332, n. 74 (Aalen 1969) (addition by P.
Weimar).
n12. See generally, e.g., Kantorowicz, supra note 11, at 216. The definition
of Martinus is based on Cicero, Topica 4 23: "Valeat aequitas, quae paribus in
causis paria iura desiderat." (Bornecque ed., p. 73).
n13. See A. Gouron, Die Entstehung der franzosischen Rechtsschule. Summa
Iustiniani est in hoc opere und Tubinger Rechtsbuch, ZRG Rom. 93, 138-160
(1976). See generally, A. Gouron, La science du droit dans le Midi de la
France au Moyen Age, No. IX, (1984). But cf., La Summa Institutionum "Iustiniani
est in hoc opere' 19 (P. Legendre ed., 1973) ("Equitas est rerum convenientia,
que cuncta coequiparat in paribus causis paria iura desiderans."). See E.M.
Meijers, Le Conflit entre L'equite et La Loi chez Les premiers glossateurs,
TRG 17, 117-141 (1941) (for equity in the early works
of the glossators). See also 4 E.M. Meijers, Etudes D'Histoire du Droit
142-156. See also 2 M. Boulet-Sautel, Equite, Justice
et Droit Chez les Glossateurs du XIIe Siecle. Recueils de Memoires et Travaux
1-11, 27 (1951). See also 2 E. Cortese, La Norma Giuridica 322, n.43 and 44
(1964).
n14. See H. Lange, Ius aequum und ius strictum bei den glossatorem,
Zeitschrift fur Rechtsegeschichte (Rom.) 71, 329-347 (1954) [hereinafter ZRG];
See also Das Romische Recht im Mittelalter 89-115, (F.J.H. Schrage ed.,
Darmstadt 1987). See also IV E.M. Meijers, Etudes D'Histoire du Droit 147 with
a gloss from Marhnus already edited by Savigny, Geschichte des Romischen
Rechts im Mittelalter, [su'2']1850 48618f; Cortese op. cit. II, 321, n.42.
n15. C.32, q.6 pr.: "Unde, cum Iudei adulteram accusarent, equitatis
sententiam a domino acceperunt." In Gratian's Dictum p. C. 11, q. 3, c. 90 an
illicit order of a prelate is called "contra equitatem sententia.'
n16. C.25, q.1, c.25 and C.25, q.2, c.21.
n17. See W. Holtzmann, Kanonistische Erganzungen zur Italia pontificia, 67 QF
76 (1958) 76. The decretal was added to Gratian's Decretum in some early
manuscripts of the 12th century; obviously it was immediately used as valid
law by the decretists. See also J. Rambaud-Buhot, L'Abbreviatio Decreti
d'Omnebene, in Proceedings of the Sixth International Congress of Medieval
Canon Law, 7 Monumenta Iuris Canonici 93-107 (1985) (for Omnebene, author of
an Abbreviatio of Gratian's Decretum). See Ch. Lefebvre, in L'Age Classique (7
Histoire du Droit et des Institutions de l'Eglise en Occident (Le Bras et al.
eds., 1965)) (p. 407 wrongly attributes this decretal to Pope Honorius II).
n18. Stephen of Tournai, Prologus to the Summa 118 (H. Kalb ed., Studien zur
Summa Stephans von Tournai 1983): "Item quedam capitula data sunt ex rigore,
quedam ex dispensatione vel equitate."
n19. See G. Conklin, Stephen of Tournai and the Development of aequitas
canonica; The Theory and Practice of Law after Gratian, in Proceedings of the
Eighth International Congress of Medieval Canon Law, San Diego 1988, 369-386
(1992). Conklin is the first author to use Stephen's letters as source for
Stephen's doctrine of equity.
n20. Summa "Elegantius in iure divino' seu Coloniensis, Monumenta Iuris
Canonici and G. Frasen 16 (S. Kuttner ed., ser. A, Vol. 1, 1969).
n21. See G. Conklin, Stephen of Tournai and Aequitas canonica, supra note 19,
at 380. The text is found in Stephen Epistola, Lettres d'Etienne de Tournai
184, 225 (J. Desilve ed., Paris 1893). Stephen's formulation is taken over
from Cod. 1.14.1.
n22. X 1.29.13 (JL 13877).
n23. X 2.12.5.
n24. Derived from Cod.2.50.1; see G.W. Wetzell, System des ordentlichen
Civil-processes 672 (Leipzig 1878).
n25. X 1.41.6; see Wetzell, supra note 24, at 673.
n26. X 1.36.11; see also Ch. Lefebvre, Les pouvoirs du juge en droit danonique
181 (Paris 1938).
n27. Lefebvre, supra note 26, at 185.
n28. Bernhard, Glossa ordinaria ad X 1.36.11 v. "aequitate.' See also Lefebvre,
supra note 26, at 186.
n29. Johannes Teutonicus, Glossa Ordinaria Ad C.1, q.7, c.17.
n30. These three definitions by Hostiensis are found in his Summa (Lyon ed.,
1537, reprint 1962) lib. V, De dispensationibus, no. 1 (fol. 289 r b).
n31. Ch. Lefebvre, "Aequitas canonica' et "periculum animae' dans la doctrine
de L'Hostiensis, Ephemerides iuris canonici 8, 305-321 (1952). The connection
between aequitas and periculum animae can already be found in the letters of
Stephen of Tournai, see Conklin, supra note 19, at 384.
n32. Norbert Horn, Aequitas in den Lehren des Baldus 61 (Forschungen zur
neueren Privatrechtsgeschichte 11, 1968).