Rivista internazionale di diritto comune
19 (2008)
kenneth
pennington
Torture and Fear: Enemies of Justice
After a long
hiatus torture is once again a part of American experience[1].
As Jeremy Waldron has eloquently written[2]:
It is
dispiriting as well as shameful to have to turn our attention to this issue.
In 1911 the author of the article on “Torture” in the
Encyclopedia Britannica wrote that
‘the whole subject is now one of only historical interest as far as Europe is
concerned...’. Perhaps what is remarkable is not that torture is
used, but that it (or something very close to it) is being defended by
well-known American jurists and law professors... John Yoo... of Berkeley...
Alan Derschowitz... <of> Harvard... Jay Bybee... <of the> Ninth Circuit Court.
Other scholars
have raised their voices to protest this lamentable chapter of recent American
history. John Langbein recently reissued his book on torture in early modern
Europe with the sobering reflection[3]:
The European
law of torture... was one of the worst blunders in the administration of
justice in all of Western history... The abiding lesson is that coercion is
the enemy of truth, and that efforts to tolerate and regulate coercion in the
service of truth have routinely failed across the ages.
Most recently
Phillippe Sands has written a book that thoroughly explores the history of the
“torture memos” in the Bush administration, especially those generated with
the approval of Donald Rumsfeld and his team of lawyers. It will be a valuable
resource for future tribunals that will prosecute Americans who have
resurrected and sanctioned torture for crimes against humanity[4].
Perhaps the most
disheartening part of the story about the American use of torture in the first
years of the twenty-first century is the pervasive silence of American
churches. Religious leaders in the United States seem to suffer from the same
moral blindness on this issue as their political leaders[5].
The United States
Department of Justice has continued to produce secret memos that reportedly
defend harsh (“enhanced”) interrogation techniques. Journalists are reporting
more about the atrocities committed at Abu Ghraib and elsewhere[6].
If Jeremy Waldron had known of the legal opinions produced in 2005 and
testimony to Congress in 2008 by Steven G. Bradbury he would have included him
in his list of shame. Public opprobrium and a mantle of shame, however, do not
seem to deter American advocates of torture. In January of 2008 the Bush
administration continued to push for Bradbury’s elevation to the post of chief
of the Justice Department’s Office of Legal Counsel[7].
Shortly afterwards yet another of the Bush administration’s Attorneys General
has declared that he and the president might declare torture legal under
certain circumstances[8].
Finally, Michael Hayden, the director of the Central Intelligence Agency,
confirmed the worst kept secret in Washington that the United States had
tortured “only three detainees” with waterboarding[9].
Those people who believed that number were offered free season passes to
Disney Land[10].
An American president and his attorneys general, law professors and judges are
only the latest who could be inscribed on Alessandro Manzoni’s (1785-1873)
Column of Infamy, the Italian
novelist’s passionate attack on Milanese judges who had tortured innocent
victims illegally[11].
Fear has played a
key role in the history of torture. It has provided reasons to torture and has
defined what is torture. In the United States, fear, especially of the ticking
bomb scenario, has many devoted disciples. Long before American politicians
began to use fear as a weapon of thought control Judith Shklar worried about
government’s using “acute fear” to oppress their people[12].
The American president, attorneys general, and other members of the government
have used fear as a central argument to defend its use of torture against the
prisoners it holds. “Fear” in this sense of the word is a general concept
without much precision. The Roman jurists were the first to develop
sophisticated definitions of fear in law, and they applied their understanding
of fear to many different legal problems. Their thought shaped medieval and
early modern conceptions of torture. Fear has inspired the use of torture;
fear also has played a role in historical discussions of torture.
I shall make
the following points in this essay. 1. Torture has always had a shabby
reputation and has never been trusted as a reliable method of obtaining
evidence from the very beginnings of its appearance in jurisprudence. 2. Fear
of torture has been considered torture for almost 700 years. 3. Torture has
always been limited in every legal system that has used it lawfully. 4. The
courts have generally used torture to confirm evidence, not to produce
evidence. 5. Lastly, people who are ignorant of torture’s history,
jurisprudence, and practice have drafted treaties, written memos, and approved
its use against other human beings. I will argue that the history of torture
provides much evidence that it is a fatally flawed procedure for producing
evidence that can be used in the courtroom. We should be morally outraged by a
government that permits torture and by a judicial system or government agency
that uses torture. However, an equally strong argument can be made against
torture on practical grounds. After centuries of practice, jurists who had
seen and lived with torture in the judicial system decided that it just did
not work.
Torture has long
been seen as barbaric practice. Whenever people have thought about its
origins, they have been convinced that its creators must have been evil. A
thirteenth-century commentator on Dante’s
Commedia, Jacobus della Lana, named
Tarquinius Superbus, the tyrannical last king of Rome, the inventor of
torture, and Albericus de Rosate († 1360) canonized the claim in his
commentary on the section of Justinian’s
Digest devoted to torture. Jurists in the sixteenth and seventeenth
centuries were happy to repeat the story[13].
The Romans accused Tarquinius of many crimes, but they never accused him of
inventing torture.
Although the
Greeks employed torture, they had no jurisprudence that discussed torture.
Consequently, any attempt to examine the history of torture must begin with
Roman jurisprudence. As Americans have done today, the Romans tortured people
to defend the state. In cases of
treason torture was always permitted during the empire.
It was also used to preserve the virtue and honor of the Roman family.
Although free men could be tortured
only when they plotted treason, slaves could be tortured to uncover the sexual
crimes of their mistresses (as well as for other crimes). However, the Romans
did not use torture indiscriminately. They established limits to its use.
From the first
century before the Common Era, Roman jurists began to struggle with the
questions that have been repeated through the centuries. What is torture? Can
torture provide reliable information? Ancient Roman jurists were the first to
understand that fear was an important element that defined torture. Two words
were most commonly used for torture: “quaestio” and “tormentum”. Sometimes the
term “quaestio tormentis” was employed to distinguish “quaestio” from its more
general meaning “to investigate <a crime>”[14].
In a passage in Justinian’s Digest
Ulpian defined torture[15]:
We ought to
understand “quaestio” as “tormenta” (tortures) when the body is subjected to
pain in order to discover the truth. Questioning persons and subjecting them
to trivial fear are not covered by this edict. The word “quaestio” also
encompasses what they call terrible confinements (mala mansio). When a person
is questioned with force and torture, this is understood to be “quaestio”.
The Roman jurists
were careful to calibrate what constituted fear (formido, metus, pavor, timor,
territio, or trepidatio) and created the first jurisprudence of terror.
“Metus” was the word they most often used in legal texts. They considered fear
in many areas of law. The Praetorian Edict in its final form declared that “I
will not hold valid what has been done because of fear”[16].
In the second century Gaius defined fear as “not being what a person without
sound judgment might feel but what could have an effect on a person of the
most resolute behavior (homo
constantissimus)”[17].
The “homo constans” or “homo diligens” had slightly different meanings
depending on the area of law[18].
In general the jurists used it to describe an adult male whose judgment was
grounded in maturity and reason. Gaius emphasized that the reasonable man was
not simply a “stable person” but the “most stable person”. The fear of
torture, in other words, was not that which was felt by the faint-hearted or
even the average person. The “heroic” person must fear the threat.
Ulpian’s “mala
mansio” provides some insight into Roman thinking about the treatment of those
accused of serious crimes. Although “mala mansio” has been defined by some
scholars as an instrument of torture ― a place can be an instrument of torture[19]
― the only other text in the Digest
where the term is used seems to consider it a place and distinguish it from
the means by which the captive was held[20].
The Romans were aware, in other words, that imprisonment could be a form of
torture. In 320 the Emperor Constantine issued a statute that laid down
principles for the treatment of defendants who have been confined. He began by
focusing on the rights of defendants to a quick trial[21]:
When a
defendant has been produced publicly in any case, whether the accuser brought
him or whether public authorities produced him, the criminal court should hear
his case immediately. If he is guilty, he may be punished, and if he is
innocent, he may be freed.
In the same
statute Constantine established norms for imprisonment. If it were necessary
to bind defendants with chains because of the seriousness of the accusation
they should be of sufficient length that they do not suffer. There should not
be any suffering in prison; rather confinement should be secure[22].
Defendants should never be kept in places that are dark and without light. On
the contrary prisoners have a right to the light of the sun. Constantine
emphasized that no one should die in custody, especially since the prisoner
might be innocent[23].
Jailers cannot sell their services to accusers by delaying hearings or letting
their charges suffer from illness[24].
Judges who fail to punish jailers who commit these crimes will not only lose
their reputations but will confront the “fear of danger”[25].
The Romans
famously used torture, but they limited its use in judicial proceedings. Free
Romans could not be tortured except for very serious crimes[26].
Further, from the beginning the jurists were skeptical of its effectiveness.
In the third century Ulpian expressed his doubts about torture in a passage
that Justinian’s jurists included in the
Digest[27]:
It is stated in
our constitutions that trust should not always be given to torture, but
torture should not always be rejected. Torture is a weak and dangerous thing
that may fail the truth. Many people have the patience and endurance to be
contemptuous of torture. The truth can never be extracted from them. Others
have so little patience that they would rather tell any kind of lie than
suffer torture. They confess to anything by implicating themselves and others
in crimes.
The Roman jurists’
ideas about torture are not of just antiquarian interest. They shaped European
jurisprudence and thought until the eighteenth century. Ulpian's and
Constantine’s texts became an integral part of the body of material that every
law student studied from the twelfth century on. Students were reminded for
centuries that torture was a “res fragilis et periculosa”; Ulpian’s lapidary
conclusion about torture’s failures were repeated by the European jurists from
Accursius to Bartolus to Beccaria[28].
Doubts about
torture can be found outside legal sources. Christian writers connected
Pilate’s flagellation of Jesus with torture. Tertullian railed against the use
of torture against Christians, but he condemned torture as a means to force
Christians to recant, not as a judicial institution[29].
Could a Christian judge torture? Bishop Exuperius of Toulouse wrote to Pope
Innocent I (401-417) and asked what should be done with a baptized Christian
who had tortured and executed defendants. Innocent responded that this
question had not yet been answered by his predecessors. He concluded that
since God had established the office of judge, a Christian could justly carry
out the duties of his office, even if it meant torturing defendants and
executing the guilty[30].
In an overlooked
passage St. Cyprian of Carthage (ca. 250 C.E.) connected torture with the
injustices committed in Roman courts of law[31].
He wrote a letter to his friend Donatus about the state of the Roman courts.
If he were alive today his condemnation might have appeared in
The New York Times[32].
His main concerns were the courts’ and judges’ disregard of the fundamental
principles of law and their condoning the use of torture. Cyprian told his
friend that although he might expect to find that the courts were free from
lawlessness and criminality, he would be wrong[33]:
Even in the
place where the Twelve Tables are engraved and statutes are displayed on brass
tablets, crimes are committed against the laws, and the principles of justice
are violated. Innocence is not preserved there where it should be defended.
Cyprian makes a
distinction between “lex” and “ius” in this passage that is important and is
not just an example of elegant variation. “Lex” was a particular mandate of
the Roman civil law; “ius” was a far richer term. It had within its penumbras
of meanings principles of Roman jurisprudence and justice.
Cyprian lamented
that the Roman forum roared with the madness of litigation. The spear, the
sword, and the executioner always stand there at the ready. He conjured a
vision of a forum filled with tearing hooks (ungula),
stretching racks (eculeus), and
burning fires that torture the body in more places than the body has limbs[34].
In the Roman courts no one fears the laws; no one fears the quaestor; no one
fears the judge since the decision can be brought without fear. Among the
guilty to be innocent has become a crime[35].
Cyprian did not
doubt torture; he abhorred it. St. Augustine (354-430) expanded upon Ulpian’s
qualms about torture. In The City of God
Augustine emphasized the danger that innocent people would be tortured[36]:
Of the error of
human judgments when the truth is hidden.
What shall I
say of torture applied to the accused himself? He is tortured to discover
whether he is guilty, so that, though innocent, he suffers a severe punishment
for crime that is still doubtful, not because it is proved that he committed
it, but because it is not known that he did not commit it. And through this
ignorance of the judge, the innocent man suffers... And the judge thinks it
not contrary to divine law that innocent witnesses are tortured in cases
dealing with the crimes of others... or that the accused are put to the
torture and, though innocent, make false confessions regarding themselves, and
are punished; or that, though they be not condemned to die, they often die
during the torture.
The Roman
jurists thought that torture was to be used only on slaves or for particularly
heinous crimes like treason and could be gauged by the amount of fear it
produced. Torture was of uncertain value as an instrument for producing
evidence. Cyprian and Augustine agreed that torture was fallible, immoral, and
punished the innocent which led to even more evil.
Even though
judicial torture might seem out of place in the world of the Germanic ordeal,
it did not completely disappear during the early Middle Ages[37].
At least some described the ordeal itself as torture[38].
The ordeal gradually disappeared during the twelfth and early thirteenth
centuries. Its place was taken by a mode of proof called the
Ordo iudiciarius. The history of how
the Romano-canonical process, the ordo
iudiciarius, became the model for the courts of continental legal systems
remains to be written. We can say with certainty that its roots predate the
Fourth Lateran Council (1215 A.D.) that forbade clerical participation in the
ordeal. From at least 1150 on, when the evidence becomes plentiful, church
courts all over Europe had almost completely abandoned the ordeal as a mode of
proof for deciding ecclesiastical cases. This fact is attested by the vast
number of twelfth-century papal decretals that describe implicitly and
sometimes explicitly the procedures of the
ordo iudiciarius that were, by then,
well established[39].
The centralization
of papal legislative and judicial power in the eleventh century had introduced
far-reaching changes in how ecclesiastical justice functioned. The
Dictatus papae of Pope Gregory VII
stipulated that “no one shall dare to condemn one who appeals to the apostolic
chair” (n. 20). Appeal from the decision of an ordeal the judgment of God was
logically impossible. The inexorable logic of the pope's dictum demanded that
the old systems of proof not be used. As the papal court became the court of
last resort, ecclesiastical procedure had to adapt to a system of proof that
was based on evidence. By the 1130s Pope Innocent II inveighed against bishops
who hindered appeals to Rome and levied heavy fines if they obstructed
litigants from appealing to Rome. Papal letters of the twelfth century
pullulate with references to witnesses and their testimony. Sometime before
1133-1136, Bulgarus, the famous doctor of Roman law, wrote a short
ordo that summarized the rules of procedure for Haimeric, the papal
chancellor[40].
In the twelfth
century, the ordo iudiciarius was
new and dangerous to local interests, usurping the authority of the community
to render justice. The new procedure would not have been victorious if it had
not offered better justice than the old system. By the second half of the
twelfth century, criticism of one form of local justice, the ordeal, was
prevalent and persuasive[41].
Finally, the Fourth Lateran Council forbade clerical participation in the
liturgy of the ordeal (c. 18). Paradoxically, at a time when some historians
have seen medieval conceptions of due process rapidly being eroded by the
introduction of torture and by a fierce determination of ecclesiastical and
secular magistrates to eradicate crime, the jurists rethought the origins of
the judicial process. As they did defendants' rights became a central issue.
In the twelfth century the ordo
iudiciarius was a mode of proof that demanded that there be an accuser.
Judges or magistrates could not initiate an accusation. During the second half
of the twelfth century the right of a bishop to investigate wrong-doing was
gradually established in ecclesiastical courts. Innocent III established the
legitimacy of this new procedure, the “inquisition (inquisitio),”
in several decretal letters and gave it a permanent place in the
ordo iudiciarius with the canon
Qualiter et quando at the Fourth
Lateran Council (c.8).
Scholars long
believed that Innocent and his curia invented the inquisitorial procedure.
Lotte Kéry has demonstrated (contra Trusen
et alii) that prelates had been
ordered to investigate (inquisitio veritatis) since the pontificate of Pope Alexander III
(1159-1181)[42].
By the end of the pontificate of Innocent III (1216) the obligation and the
duty of bishops to prosecute clerical crimes had become firmly established as
an important part of ecclesiastical procedure.
A signpost for the
development of the inquisitorial procedure is the birth of an important maxim
of criminal law, “publicae utilitatis intersit ne crimina remaneant impunita”
(It is in the interest of the public good that crimes do not remain
unpunished) during the pontificate of Pope Innocent III. “Ne crimina remaneant
impunita” became a standard maxim of the Ius commune in the later Middle Ages.
It was used by the jurists to signal the duty that princes and judges had to
prosecute crime[43].
The creation of
the new “inquisition” raised questions about a procedure in which third
parties brought accusations and in which judges began to play a more active
role in prosecuting crime. It changed concepts of justice in European courts.
It has been argued that the new inquisitorial procedure led to the general use
of torture in judicial procedure in order to bring a full proof to the
courtroom[44].
To a certain extent, it seems true that the jurists gave the “common good” of
people’s right to have criminals’ punished equal standing with the rights of
the human person in criminal procedure. The “common good” justified torture
and trumped a defendant’s presumption of innocence.
We do not know how
or exactly when torture became an accepted part of the
ordo iudiciarius[45].
In canon law torture had always been prohibited, and Gratian (ca. 1140) left
no doubt about its illegality in ecclesiastical courts[46].
As will become clear in this essay, I believe that medieval and early modern
jurists were always careful to limit torture in judicial proceedings. It never
became an accepted and normal part of criminal law in every case. We do know
that during the thirteenth century torture began to be employed as a means of
obtaining evidence and confirming confessions. In the first half of the
thirteenth centuries Italian city states began to regulate torture in their
courts. By the 1220s some jurists had become sharply critical of judges who
indiscriminately and unlawfully used torture in their courts without observing
the strict rules governing when torture could be used and on whom torture
could be applied. In the Italian city states, the jurists were particularly
concerned to exempt citizens from torture and to define who could be tortured[47].
With that said we have not much evidence about the use of torture in the
thirteenth century. Until the surviving court records are explored we will not
have much information about how practice conformed to theory. Only the court
records of the Italian archives will reveal whether the strict limitations on
torture in theory were observed in practice.
In 1241 the
city-state of Vercelli promulgated a statute that “no man [citizen of
Vercelli] is to be tortured”[48].
A marginal gloss to this statute in the margin noted[49]:
The podestà or
rector is held to observe this law without exception or dispensation and to
enforce its observance... The podestà or rector ought to swear an oath to
uphold these provisions.
Fiorelli has
studied the statutes of the Italian city-states and found that almost all of
them had statutes that limited the use of torture on citizens of good
reputation[50].
Johannes Andreae († 1348) was a layman who taught canon law at Bologna and
was, with Bartolus of Sassoferrato († 1357), the most influential jurist in
the first half of the fourteenth century. He wrote glosses to the most
important and most extensive treatise on procedure produced during the Middle
Ages, Guillielmus Durantis’ Speculum
iudiciale (ca. 1291). He noted that the statutes of the city-states
prohibited torture unless there were grave presumptions of guilt (violentae praesumptiones)[51].
Johannes’ generalization was supported by the statutes of Bologna that were
promulgated in 1288. The people of Bologna (populus
Bononie) who belonged to a guild or who had membership because of a
privilege, statute, ordinance, decree or statute could not be tortured without
legitimate proofs (legittime probationes) or grave presumptions (violentae
presumptiones) or clear and obvious evidence (manifesta
indicia)[52].
The Captain of the People had to examine the evidence and approve the use of
torture in the presence of one of the defendant’s family, six “anziani
(elders)” or consuls. Four officials of the commune should hear the
confessions extracted under torture and a notary must be present to record
them in writing. Without these safeguards, the statute concluded, torture
could not be used. If these provisions were violated the podestà would be
condemned to pay 1000 Bolognese pounds. He would also be thrown out of the
government[53].
In the Southern
Italian Norman kingdom (Regno), Emperor Frederick II was the first to
legislate the use of torture in some detail, although he was not the first
medieval ruler to deal with torture in his
Constitutiones that honor seems to
have gone to the city-state of Verona in 1228[54].
He published a constitution in 1231 in a title of his legal code that dealt
with crimes committed secretly[55]:
If from a
judge’s investigation base persons are accused of homicide, although a full
proof was not produced against any of them, we decree that these base and
servile persons should be subjected to torture. If through these measures the
court cannot establish the guilt of the persons because strong persons who
undergo the great and accustomed power of torture do not confess or because of
their weakness, as we know often happens, the timid and fearful confess but do
not repeat their confessions in court after having been taken away from the
torture, which they do not fear to be repeated...
The jurists who
drafted this statute adhered closely to the rules established by the ancient
Roman jurists[56].
Frederick echoed Ulpian’s doubts about the efficacy of torture. Only the lower
classes of society could be tortured. He anticipated that the guilty persons
would not be found, torture notwithstanding. If no one confessed to the crime
his final depository clause in the statute fined the place in which the murder
took place: the inhabitants must pay a fine of 100 gold augustales if a
Christian had been murdered; 50 if a Moslem or a Jew. If torture did not work
to bring criminals to justice, he punished the entire community and among
them, the innocent. Collective guilt and punishing the innocent were not alien
to medieval legal and theological thought[57].
Later jurists and kings of the Regno
left a paper trail on torture that stretches into the late Middle Ages. In the
sixteenth century Jacobus Anellus de Bottis, a Neapolitan royal counselor
wrote that Frederick’s constitution was odious[58].
Earlier, Andreas de Isernia († 1316) limited torture and its use
significantly. Evidence of wrongdoing was required before anyone could be
tortured. If a person confessed to a crime under torture without there having
been sufficient evidence that indicated his guilt, his confession was invalid
and inadmissible in court, even if he confirmed his confession later when he
was free from the threat of torture. Perseverance in his testimony cannot
change an illegal act into a legal one[59].
Andreas thought that if there were sufficient proof of guilt, the strength of
those proofs should determine whether the defendant could be tortured more
than once. “A good judge should take everything into consideration:” He must
decide whether the defendant was strong or weak, the persuasiveness of the
proofs, and the nature of the crime. If, however, there were doubts, the judge
should be inclined to be milder, which is holier[60].
King Charles II († 1309) issued legislation that confirmed all the points of
Andreas’ gloss[61].
He also established the right of appeal from a judge’s decision to torture a
defendant[62].
A judge and his officials could be condemned to death if a person died under
torture without having been granted the right of appeal[63].
King John († 1479) eliminated torture from the court completely. He
promulgated a statute in which he declared that torture could only be carried
out after the conclusion of a trial. No superior could grant a judge the right
to torture persons unless the defendant had already been sentenced by the
judgment of a court (torture as punishment was acceptable). The only exception
was in a trial for treason. John may be the first European monarch who
(almost) banned torture from the courtroom. In theory the courts of the
Kingdom of the Two Sicilies torture could no longer provide evidence[64].
Richard Fraher has
written a series of articles on the connection between torture the
inquisitorial procedure[65].
He has vigorously pressed a thesis that both in theory and practice torture
was used indiscriminately in the courts of the
Ius commune from the thirteenth
century on. The jurists, he has argued, were more concerned with punishing
crimes than protecting the rights of defendants. In one essay he presented a
late thirteenth-century jurist, Albertus Gandinus, as hell-bent on urging
judges to use torture in their courts. Albertus, he said, “espoused an almost
bloodthirsty enthusiasm” for torture[66].
He advocated torturing defendants even though there was not any substantial
proof they were guilty. Fraher came to this conclusion from Albertus’ treatise
De maleficiis that circulated widely
after it was finished ca. 1300[67].
Albertus had posited a hypothetical in which a man of low birth was captured
and accused of a crime. The question was whether the defendant could be
tortured if there were only vague voices of “public report (fama)
and clamor” that pointed towards his guilt. Albertus solved his hypothetical
using the typical “sic et non” format that the jurists loved. Fraher took all
of his evidence from the section of the treatise that argued that the judge
could torture the defendant without sufficient proofs[68].
Albertus, however, rendered his opinion not there but in his conclusion (solutio)[69].
He argued that the defendant could only be tortured if there were witnesses
who were prudent and honest, who presented concrete, specific evidence, and
who did not represent a minority of the population but the “maior pars”.
Further the defendants’ base reputation should have arisen before the crime
had been committed, not after[70].
If Fraher had read
the section of Albertus’ treatise where the jurist discussed torture he would
have also come to very different conclusions[71].
At the beginning of the title on torture Albertus made five points: 1. a judge
who intended to use torture had to consider the law and issues of humanity. If
there were less cruel ways to discover the truth the judge must take them[72].
2. Not all crimes and not every reason should lead to torture; not all persons
are subject to torture[73].
3. Not just any evidence produces a reason to torture. The evidence should be
so strong that the only thing lacking is a confession[74].
4. Torture should never be repeated unless two things are present: new
evidence and a person who is strong enough to endure a repetition of torture[75].
5. Torture should be moderate. The judge should not torture according to the
demands of an accuser. The tortured person should remain healthy for either a
decision declaring his innocence or for his punishment[76].
Albertus also
broached what must have been a new issue: whether the defendant had a right to
appeal a judge’s decision that imposed torture by claiming that he had new
evidence to present to the court. Albertus was unsure whether that was
possible. There was no provision in Roman law for appealing a judge’s
decision. He consulted Lambertus Ramponi, a distinguished Roman law professor
(1269-1304) in Bologna[77].
Lambertus told Albertus that an appeal could be made and referred to a text in
the Digest that did not quite answer the question[78].
Albertus concluded, with Lambertus’ concurrence, that a defense was always
given priority “because if the defense was deferred until after torture, the
defendant could never recover the damage to his limbs”[79].
King Charles II’s legislation in Sicily that granted appeals from torture was
promulgated about the same time as Albertus was writing his treatise (ca.
1290). The medieval jurists were shaping jurisprudence of torture and
influencing legislation.
Albertus raised
yet another question. Could a podestà torture a man who was accused of murder
without any evidence of his guilt? And if he could, would the defendant’s
confession constitute a full and valid confession that would permit his
condemnation? His answer was a firm no[80].
“What follows from an act lacking legitimacy cannot be valid”[81].
Albertus turned then to a more subtle question[82]:
But I pose the
question here what of the confession made under the fear of torture? I think
if <the facts of the case were>: the person to be tortured is led to the place
of the torture, his hands are bound behind him, and the judge would say to him
unless he confesses immediately he would torture him. In this case if he
confesses the confession is not valid, unless he would persevere in his
confession <in court>. The law holds such a confession extorted by fear to be
the equivalent to one extracted by torture.
Albertus explored
fear and torture. “What if,” he asked, “the person were led to the torture
chamber, but his hands were not bound behind him, <is his confession valid>?”
Although there were differing opinions, he thought the confession was not
admissible in court[83].
He posed another question to define exactly what constituted the fear in a
reasonable man (homo constans)[84]:
But what if
outside the torture chamber the judge said, “either you confess or I shall
lead you to be tortured,” trying to create as much terror in him as he could?
The defendant confessed. Will it be said in this case that the confession was
extorted by fear? I say no, because this was slight terror... we ought to
interpret terror or fear of torture as a present and immediate <threat of
torture>... Slight terror of torture outside the torture chamber is an
illusory fact.
Albertus tried
to calibrate the amount of fear that constitutes torture. His solution was to
distinguish between “an imminent and apparent danger” of torture to use the
terminology of current American criminal law and the mere threat of torture.
How did torture
work in the real world, outside the handbooks of the jurists and the teachings
of the classroom? We only have small windows into the torture chambers of
Europe from the texts that have been published. Much more work has to be done.
Although there were certainly rogue judges – the jurists mention them
frequently – the evidence that we do have indicates that the norms established
by the jurists of the Ius commune
were observed[85].
A case that Hermann Kantorowicz published from the Bolognese archives
illustrates this point[86].
In December 1299 Vecto, the criminal judge of the Podestà of Bologna, began an
investigation of Mengho, son of Ugolino, who had been accused of robbing the
store of a silk merchant. Vecto ordered a knight (miles) Lazario to conduct an
investigation. On the 5th of December Lazario supervised the testimony of nine
witnesses and had their testimony recorded. Some of them reported that Mengho
was a robber and had a bad reputation. Others claimed that they thought that
Mengho was good or that they did not know him. Several testified that Mengho
was suspected of the crime. The evidence was, in other words, mixed.
On the same day
Lazario and a notary searched Mengho’s house. They found four skeins of silk.
It was identified as the stolen goods. Mengho was brought before Vecto at the
bench for criminal offenses next to the new city hall in Bologna. Vecto
questioned him about the evidence and the crime. The testimony of the
witnesses was read to Mengho in Italian. He denied everything. On the 7th of
December Mengho was tortured under the supervision of four magistrates and a
notary. He confessed, and the notary recorded his confession. More goods were
recovered. Once he had admitted to stealing the silk, Mengho confessed to
numerous other crimes. On the same day, he confirmed his confessions before
the court and judge Vecto. His confession added or subtracted nothing to the
written report of the notary who had heard his confession under torture.
Mengho persisted and persevered in his confession when he repeated it before
the court. The stolen goods were returned to their owner. Mengho was condemned
to the gallows and hanged.
This case
illustrates many of the norms of inquisitorial criminal procedure in secular
courts. The judge could order investigations on the authority of his office.
He had the power to conduct searches and to summon witnesses for
interrogation. If there were grave presumptions and evidence of guilt and if a
defendant refused to confess, the defendant could be tortured to confirm his
guilt that was already proven by the evidence. Torture, however, should be
used only as a last resort, and should be preceded by powerful evidence of
guilt in this case provided by the skeins of silk found in Mengho’s house. The
conflicting testimony of the witnesses was probably not sufficient for
torture, but the discovery of the silk in Mengho’s home gave Vecto the right
to send Mengho to the torture chamber. As we have already seen, the norms of
the Ius commune and the statutes of many Italian city states forbade
indiscriminate and arbitrary torture without evidence that created a grave
presumption of guilt.
Modern scholars
have doubted that the limitations that the jurists imposed on the use of
torture had much effect in practice. However, there is growing evidence that
European criminal courts used torture sparingly. Kantorowicz published the
records of ca. 143 criminal cases from the Bolognese archives between 1284 and
1299. Of these he found evidence of torture in four cases[87].
In his study of criminal inquests in Marseille, Daniel Smail found one case of
torture in 83 fourteenth-century inquests and no evidence of torture in
“several dozen surviving cases of criminal appeals”[88].
Steven Bednarski has examined over 1500 criminal inquests between 1340 and
1403 in the small Provençal town of Manosque. He discovered only four cases in
which the defendants were tortured – and all four were foreigners[89].
In Northern France, Claude Gauvard’s examination of fifteenth-century court
records of the Parlement of Paris and the Châtelet of Paris revealed that
torture was used twenty times in 600 cases[90].
Langbein has listed 81 cases of torture in England between 1540 and 1640 but
gives no evidence about what percentage these cases might represent[91].
Richard Mowery Andrews has pointed out the after the
Ordonnance criminelle of 1670 torture almost disappeared from French
judicial procedure[92].
This evidence should begin to give pause to those scholars who have claimed
that inquisitorial procedure and the standard of proof in the
Ius commune inevitably led to the
use of torture in the courts[93].
Or that even more benighted idea, torture replaced the ordeal in medieval
courts[94].
Baldus de Ubaldis
(† 1400) underlined the importance of evidence when he discussed a cause
célèbre of the late fourteenth century[95].
The Queen of Aragon, Sibílla Fortià, had been married to Pedro IV (1336-1387)
and was the stepmother of Pedro’s son, Juan I (1387-1395). Juan entertained
doubts about Sibílla and soon after he ascended the throne brought her to
trial for practicing black magic that he said affected his health[96].
The case must have attracted attention far outside Aragon because Baldus was
commissioned to write a consilium about the legality of how Sibílla was
treated by the court[97].
The case was
perfect for the international gossip trade. Her stepson was reputed to be
effete and profligate; Sibílla was endowed, it was thought, with magical
powers. Her crimes were not only sorcery but also treason. The first question
that Baldus raised was whether a queen could be tortured. He rehearsed the
legal norms with which we are already familiar. No one could be tortured
without firm evidence (indicia certa) whose authenticity cannot be doubted[98].
He quoted the Moslem philosopher Averroës: “to seek reason when we have
knowledge is an infirmity of intelligence;” if there were full proofs of
guilt, torture was unnecessary[99].
Baldus thought that Sibílla had confessed because of torture or from “probable
and necessary fear” of torture. As soon as she was free from torture and fear,
she recanted her confession. The confession was not valid unless she had
repeated it when there was not the terror of torture[100].
Baldus quoted a Christian theologian: “As Albertus Magnus said, a free person
must have a free mind and a free tongue”[101].
What constitutes just fear? Baldus asked. “A just fear is to be afraid of the
cruelty or the criminal (capitalis) hostility of a powerful person... Fear and
extortion arise from a just reason for fearing”[102].
Baldus’ solution to whether Sibílla should have been tortured reflects his
well-known fear of offending princes especially his own[103].
“The matter should be left to the conscience of the king who should take
counsel with the saints and learned men who fear God. If he does otherwise he
sins enormously”[104].
In the second half of his consilium Baldus did make the point that even nobles
could be tortured if they practiced magic[105].
If the prosecutors of Sibílla adhered to the rules of the late
thirteenth-century Castillian codification,
Las siete partidas covering the law
of torture, they would have followed the norms (with a few exceptions) of the
Ius commune[106].
The most important
criminal lawyer of the medieval and early modern period was undoubtedly
Prospero Farinacci (1544-1618). He was probably educated in Perugia and
quickly gained experience on both sides of the bench. In 1567 he became the
general commissioner in the service of the Orsini of Bracciano; the next year
he took up residence in Rome as a member of the papal camera. However, in 1570
he was imprisoned for an unknown crime. Legal problems hounded him for the
rest of his life. He lost an eye in a fight, was stripped of his positions,
and was even accused of sodomy[107].
In spite of his difficulties, Pope Clement VIII reinstated him to the papal
court in 1596. Farinacci defended Beatrice Cenci who was accused of killing
her father in the most famous criminal case of the time[108].
He began his most important work, Praxis
et theorica criminalis, in 1581 and put the finishing touches on it by
1601[109].
Farinacci wrote
extensively about torture and the rules governing its application, summing up
the three centuries of jurisprudence governing the use of torture by judges in
the courtroom. He repeated the standard norm that the evidence establishing
the judge’s right to torture a person must be legitimate, probable, grave, and
sufficient. The judge must be almost certain of the person’s guilt before he
could order torture. He repeated the condemnation of many earlier jurists that
judges were too ready to torture. “Princes,” he proclaimed, “should not
tolerate those evil judges”[110].
The proofs necessary to torture should be grave, urgent, certain, clear, but
even clearer than the light at midday. The judge should be almost certain
(quasi certus) of the defendant’s guilt that nothing was lacking except a
confession[111].
Without substantial evidence the judge was very limited in what he could do to
a defendant. He could not torture the defendant. He could not even frighten
him. Fear of torture was, he argued, the same as torture. If the defendant was
bound or stripped as if he were to be tortured, that was torture. If a judge
acted contrary to the rules, the defendant’s confession was not valid[112].
If a man were wise and accustomed to prison the judge could terrorize him
outside the courtroom, but if the defendant were base and timid and not
accustomed to prison, then the judge could not[113].
A judge who violated the rights of defendants without legitimate evidence or
who tortured defendants savagely was liable for judgment and must be punished[114].
If a judge decided that defendants should be tortured, he must permit them to
provide a defense. They must be given the evidence against them[115].
Judges who thought that the evidence was sufficient to torture must render an
interlocutory judgment from which the defendant could appeal. Farinacci
condemned those blood thirsty judges who did not render the interlocutory
sentence in order to proceed directly to the torture chamber. The judge must
include all the reasons why he thought the evidence was sufficient for
torturing the defendant[116].
The defendant could appeal from a decree of torture and even from the threat
of torture. After an appeal from his decree or threat of torture, the judge’s
hands were bound. He could do nothing[117].
A confession extorted from a defendant by torture after an appeal was invalid[118].
Finally, Farinacci defined three grades of torture: 1. fear of torture, 2. the
defendant is bound and raised (La corda), and 3. the defendant is bound,
raised, and beaten[119].
Perhaps the most
misunderstood norm of inquisitorial procedure is when and whether torture was
used in the court. As we have seen the jurists thought that a person could be
tortured only if the evidence was, as Farinacci put it, almost certain (quasi
certus)
[120].
A number of scholars have put forward the theory that inquisitorial judges
were forced to torture in cases when the defendant had not confessed because a
confession was necessary for a full proof if there had not been two witnesses[121].
Recently James Q. Whitman has joined that camp of scholars when he completely
misread Farinacci’s views on when a judge could torture. Whitman cites a text
of Farinacci out of context to argue that even with “proofs permitting no
doubt” a judge could deliver a defendant to torture[122].
As we have seen Baldus rejected that idea two centuries before; it is no
surprise that Farinacci also firmly rejected the idea that a judge could
torture a defendant even when he had indisputable evidence of guilt[123].
There had been a
long tradition in the Ius commune
that some people were exempt from torture, especially knights, minors,
pregnant women, and nobles. Farinacci repeated the traditional teaching[124].
However, the nobility could be tortured with the permission of the prince.
Nonetheless, even with his “absolute power,” the prince could not permit
judges to torture people without adequate proofs of guilt[125].
Just as the prince could not take away a defendant’s rights of due process,
Farinacci argued that the prince’s “absolute power” would not permit him to
violate the norm that defendants could not be tortured without sufficient
proofs. If judges were to obey princely orders to torture without having
sufficient proofs, they will be brought to trial for their crime[126].
Even the pope was limited by these norms of the
Ius commune. Farinacci cleverly interpreted a letter of Pope Sixtus
V (1585-1590) to the judges in the Papal States to vitiate what might have
been the pope’s intention. Judges who obeyed the orders of the prince to
torture were subject to a penalty that fitted the circumstances of the crime (poena
extraordinaria)[127].
At the height of
his career Farinacci became involved in the most famous criminal case of the
early modern period in Rome, the trial of Beatrice Cenci for the murder of her
father, Francesco Cenci[128].
Beatrice, her lover, Olimpio Calvetti, her brothers, Giacomo and Bernardo, and
a local peasant, Marzio Catalano were all involved in the plot. The facts were
simple. Beatrice and her mother Lucrezia had been virtually imprisoned against
their wills in the Cenci fortress Rocca della Petrilla a few miles from Rieti.
Beatrice hatched a plot to kill her father. On September 9, 1598 Olimpio,
Marzio and Beatrice went into Francesco’s room, beat him, and threw him out
the window. They concocted a story that he fell from his window, but the blood
on Francesco’s sheets and bed convinced authorities otherwise. They were
brought to trial in February 1599. In the meantime Olimpio, who had fled, was
murdered. The trial dragged on and the evidence was not conclusive. Finally
Pope Clement VIII, 5 August, 1599, issued a bull permitting the torture of
Lucrezia (as a witness), Beatrice, Giacomo, and Bernardo. Torture quickly
brought confessions. Giacomo was tortured with La corda on the 7th August,
1599 for one "Credo" and confessed in the first session. On 9 August, 1599,
Lucrezia was tortured with the La corda and confessed that Beatrice and
Olimpio were responsible; Giacomo knew everything. Bernardo was too young to
be tortured but the pope’s letter put him in the torture chamber as well.
Finally on 10 August, 1599, Beatrice was tortured with the La corda for the
time that it took to recite an “Ave Maria”. In the records of the trial she is
supposed to have cried out: “Oimé, Oimé o Madonna santissima ajutame. Calateme
che voglio dire la verità”. She made a full confession. Prospero Farinacci
became Beatrice’s attorney, but he did not have much upon which he could build
a defense. Beatrice met her lawyer on 10 August, 1599. He tried to construct a
defense around Francesco’s brutal treatment and even his purported incestuous
advances against Beatrice. But there was too little evidence. On 11 September
1599 Beatrice, Giacomo and Lucrezia were beheaded. Probably because Bernardo
was only twelve, he was sent to the galleys. The papacy confiscated all the
Cenci properties.
The trial
conformed to the norms of the Ius
commune. The Cenci were one of Rome’s most ancient families. They could
not be tortured. There were no witnesses to the crime, and the evidence
against them was circumstantial. Further, Francesco had a brutal reputation
and many enemies. The evidence might have been enough to convict them in a
modern courtroom in some cases. However, only the prince’s mandate to permit
torture provided the proof that the court needed politically to condemn them.
The trial would have very likely been different if the defendants had not been
members of the nobility. The evidence, although circumstantial, was quite
strong. Angelus Aretinus de Gambilionibus († 1461) described a case in his
tract De maleficiis in which an assault without witnesses but with much
circumstantial evidence was classified as “indicia indubitata”[129].
Since the thirteenth century jurists had created hypothetical cases to
illustrate how evidence should be interpreted. Although their opinions varied,
they did grant that “indicia” did not need to be only from direct eye
witnesses[130].
If Beatrice had not been a Cenci, I suspect that she would have been condemned
without torture.
By 1600 jurists
and theologians were beginning to question torture’s morality and legality.
Mathias Schmoeckel has recently constructed a Column of Honor for those who
began to condemn torture in the early modern world, long before Beccaria and
Verri[131].
He ordains Juan Luis Vives (1493-1540) as the first to speak out against the
use of torture in his Epistola to
Erasmus. Later in the century Michel de Montaigne (1533-1592) was
inscribed on the Column[132].
In the seventeenth century Johannes Grevius (de Greve ca. 1580-1630)[133],
Friedrich von Spee (1632)[134],
and Augustin Nicolas (1682) raised their voices in protest[135].
There might be
another story about the gradual revulsion against torture. Lisa Silverman has
studied the court records in Toulouse and found that from 1600 to 1780 the
Parlement of Toulouse used torture less and less frequently[136].
Judges might have been voting with their feet, but more work on the records of
the courts must be done to know whether courts began to abandon torture before
legislatures and princes began to ban torture from the courtroom and from
their states in the eighteenth century[137].
What can history
teach us about torture? History can teach us, because we seem to have
forgotten, a number of truths that are not “res fragiles et periculosae”.
Torture has long been considered unreliable. Every judge and jurist who got a
law degree from 1100 to ca. 1700 had to ponder the third-century Roman jurist
Ulpian’s words: “It is stated in our constitutions that trust should not
always be given to torture, but torture should not always be rejected. Torture
is a weak and dangerous thing that may fail the truth”[138].
As their thought about torture evolved, they began to focus much more on
Ulpian’s second sentence than on his acceptance of judicial torture in the
first. Even when it was a part of the judicial process jurists did not think
that it was an effective method of extracting information. From ancient Rome,
to the medieval and early modern courts of the
Ius commune, the jurists created a jurisprudence that limited the
use of torture[139].
The evidence from the past is overwhelming that judges and jurists concluded
that torture might be of some value for confirming what they already knew but
was a very poor means of gathering new information. Did the jurists protest
the use of torture in the courts? There is no evidence of it. In the end,
however, jurists insisted that torture was inhumane, and, most importantly,
did not produce reliable evidence. Beginning in the fifteenth century they
began to argue for its abolishment. The success that Cesare Beccaria
(1738-1794), Pietro Verri (1728-1797), and others had in the eighteenth
century when they battled for the abolition of torture was prepared by
centuries of debate in the classroom, in law books, in the courtroom, and in
the chambers of parliaments[140].
The current
American administration believes that the international law and treaties
governing what is and what is not torture are vague. As we have seen, the
norms and definitions are vague only if one is ignorant of two thousand years
of jurisprudence[141].
In words not befitting the president of the United States, George W. Bush has
repeated the ideas of his advisors[142].
If one looks at the two main international documents upon which the law of
torture is based, we notice one thing immediately. These documents ignore two
types of torture that the jurists had unanimously defined as torture for
centuries: the fear and the threat of torture. Torture is pain and suffering,
but jurists have known and had long argued that torture was much more than
just the physical pain the torturer inflicts on human beings. The most
important international norms are the Geneva Convention and the Convention
against Torture[143]:
Geneva
Convention 3 relative to the Treatment of Prisoners of War. Geneva, 12 August
1949.
Persons taking
no active part in the hostilities, including members of armed forces who have
laid down their arms and those placed ‘hors de combat’ by sickness, wounds,
detention, or any other cause, shall in all circumstances be treated humanely,
without any adverse distinction founded on race, color, religion or faith,
sex, birth or wealth, or any other similar criteria. To this end, the
following acts are and shall remain prohibited at any time and in any place
whatsoever with respect to the above-mentioned persons: (a) violence to life
and person, in particular murder of all kinds, mutilation, cruel treatment and
torture; (b) taking of hostages; (c) outrages upon personal dignity, in
particular humiliating and degrading treatment; (d) the passing of sentences
and the carrying out of executions without previous judgment pronounced by a
regularly constituted court, affording all the judicial guarantees which are
recognized as indispensable by civilized peoples.
Convention
against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman or Degrading Treatment or Punishment
adopted December 10, 1984, S. Treaty Doc. No. 100-20 (1988), 1465 U.N.T.S. 85
PART I Article
1
For the
purposes of this Convention, the term “torture” means any act by which severe
pain or suffering, whether physical or mental, is intentionally inflicted on a
person for such purposes as obtaining from him or a third person information
or a confession, punishing him for an act he or a third person has committed
or is suspected of having committed, or intimidating or coercing him or a
third person, or for any reason based on discrimination of any kind, when such
pain or suffering is inflicted by or at the instigation of or with the consent
or acquiescence of a public official or other person acting in an official
capacity. It does not include pain or suffering arising only from, inherent in
or incidental to lawful sanctions.
If these United
Nations documents had been as clear about what was and what was not torture as
Prospero Farinacci and his predecessors had been, we might have be saved from
some of the humiliation that we have endured during the past six years.
Perhaps the most
important conclusion that we can draw from the jurists of the past is that
they thought of judicial torture only as a method of confirming evidence, not
producing it. From the ancient Roman jurists to Prospero Farinacci no jurist
who had actually witnessed torture argued that it could produce reliable
information by itself. That is the reason they put so much emphasis on having
a strong presumption of guilt with convincing evidence before a defendant
could be tortured. American misconceptions about the efficacy of torture seem
to come from a lack of experience. The wonks who have shamed the United States
seem to have learned most of what they know about torture from Jack Bauer[144].
Alessandro Manzoni
acknowledged the importance of knowing the history of torture 168 years ago.
In the debate over the use of torture in criminal proceedings Manzoni had
pointed out that Beccaria and Verri overemphasized the originality of their
contributions to the intellectual arguments underpinning their condemnation of
torture. Manzoni also thought they de-emphasized the contribution of earlier
jurists. In particular Manzoni was troubled by Beccaria’s attack on Farinacci.
As part of Manzoni’s account of a Milanese cause célèbre that I mentioned
briefly at the beginning of this essay, he described how judges in Milan had
sent several innocent men to the rack with almost no evidence of their guilt.
He pointed out that Beccaria and Verri had seriously distorted the legal
tradition when they emphasized the novelty of their own thought condemning
torture[145]:
From this
evidence and from all we know of the practice of torture in their own time,
one can undoubtedly conclude that the interpreters of criminal procedure left
the theory and practice of torture much, but much, less barbarous than they
found it. Of course it would be absurd to attribute this diminution of evil to
one cause alone, but I think that among the many causes that it would be
reasonable to count the repeated reproofs and warnings, renewed publicly,
century after century, by jurists to whom it certainly can be granted a
definite authority over the practice of the courts.
Manzoni had
extraordinary insight into how the norms governing torture evolved in European
jurisprudence. He understood the complicated dialectic through which jurists
argued with, borrowed from, and added to the thought of their predecessors
and, in their works, spoke across the centuries to their successors. He also
understood that the arguments and thought of the jurists eventually penetrated
into the rough and tumble of the courtroom and were heard in the chambers of
parliaments. Is it too much to hope that those voices from the past might
persuade an American president, the Supreme Court, the lawyers in the Justice
Department, and a number of professors in elite American law schools that
torture is an unacceptable evil? (One could also hope that they might also
rediscover the universal norms of due process and habeas corpus with their
equally strong and deep historical roots[146]).
And
that those people who formulated the policies condoning torture and those who
carried them out should be prosecuted in American courts rather than only in
foreign courts? Time will tell.
Postscript.
In April 2009, as this essay went to press, President Barack Obama
released memos written by Jay Bybee, John Yoo, and others describing in detail
the barbaric methods that Central Intelligence Agents could use on prisoners.
At a news conference on April 29, 2009, President Obama stated that the
procedures in these memos constituted torture.
He has not yet taken the next logical step of prosecuting the enablers
of torture in the United States Government criminally.
[2] Cited
by Jeremy Waldron, ‘Torture and Positive Law: Jurisprudence for the White
House’, Columbia Law Review 105
(2005) 1684-1685. Besides Waldron, other American jurists have spoken out
forcefully against torture. See the special issue of the
Case Western Reserve Journal of International Law 37 (2006) that was
devoted to essays on American torture since 2002. The Yoo memo of March 14,
2003 was released in April 2008.
[4] Philippe
Sands, Torture Team: Rumfeld’s Memo
and the Betrayal of Amercian Values (New York-Houndmills 2008).
[5] The
Catholic Church accepted the arguments of the Catholic jurists against the
use of torture that I will detail in this essay when Pope Pius VII abolished
torture from inquisitorial procedure in all tribunals after he had
established a short-lived revival of the Spanish Inquisition in 1816, see
Jean Antoine Llorente (Juan Antonio Llorente),
The History of the Inquisition of
Spain from the Time of its Establishment to the Reign of Ferdinand VII
(London 1826) 572-573.
See also the reflections of Jeremy Waldron,
“The Injury Done by Christian Silence to Public Debate over America’s
Use of Torture,”
Journal of Law, Philosophy and Culture 2 (2008) 1-22.
[6] New
Yorker, March 24, 2008, “Exposure” by Philip Gourevitch and Errol Morris,
pp. 44-57.
[9] Washington
Post, February 8, 2008, A18.
The release of a secret Red Cross report in March, 2009,
definitively proved that torture was pervasive; see Mark Danner, “US
Torture: Voices from the Black
Sites,”
The New York Review of Books 56
(April 9, 2009) 69-77. Hayden
somehow neglected to mention that these three prisioners were tortured
hundreds of times. In April, 2009 the Obama administration released
memoranda verifying that waterboarding was used 266 times on two captives
(New York Times, April 21, 2009, A1).
[40] Linda
Fowler-Magerl, Ordo iudiciorum vel ordo iudiciarius (Repertorien zur Frühzeit der
gelehrten Rechte, Ius commune, Sonderhefte 19; Frankfurt am Main 1984) 35-40
and Kenneth Pennington, ‘The “Big Bang”: Roman Law in the Early
Twelfth-Century’, Rivista
internazionale di diritto comune 18 (2007) 43-70, for the dating of
Bulgarus’ treatise and for Pope Innocent II’s decretal. The most complete
survey of the rules of procedure of the medieval “ordo iudiciarius” is
Wiesław Litewski, Der
römisch-kanonische Zivilprozeß nach den älteren ordines iudiciarii (2
Volumes; Kraków 1999).
[130] Ibid. 41-42 and 56. See also Gandinus’ discussions of “indicia indubitata” in Gandinus 2.90-98.
[131] Humanität und Staatsraison 93-186.
[132] Essays 1.22; 2.5, 11.
[133] Tribunal reformatum (Hamburg 1624).
[134] Cautio criminalis seu de processibus contra sagas liber (Frankfurt am Main 1632), published anonymously.
[135] Si la torture est un moyen seur a verifier les crimes secrets: Dissertation morale et juridique (Amsterdam 1682).
[136] Lisa Silverman, Tortured Subjects: Pain, Truth, and the Body in Early Modern France (Chicago-London 2001) 71-84.
[137] See Langbein, Torture 10, list of countries that banned torture in the eighteenth century.
[138] Dig.
48.18.1.23: “Quaestioni fidem non semper nec tamen numquam habendam
constitutionibus declaratur: etenim res est fragilis et periculosa et quae
veritatem fallat”.
[139] I am far from the first to reach the conclusion that torture was rejected before legislatures outlawed it. Every scholar who has studied the history of torture has come to similar general conclusions, although, as we have seen, they differ on exactly when torture was eliminated; see Peters, Torture 8-9; Langbein, Torture 8-10. Most recently Heikki Pihlajamäki, “The Painful Question: The Fate of Judicial Torture in Early Modern Sweden,” Law and History Review 25 (2007) 557-592.
[140] [Cesare
Beccaria], Dei delitti e delle pene
(Monaco [Livorno?] 1764), published anonymously. Pietro Verri, Osservazioni sulla tortura: E singolarmente sugli effetti che produsse
all’occasione delle unzioni malefiche, alle quali si attribuì la pestilenza
che devastò Milano l’anno 1630 (Milan 1804), published postumously.
[142] George
W. Bush, September 15, 2006 Press Conference: “This debate is occurring
because of the Supreme Court's ruling that said that we must conduct
ourselves under the Common Article 3 of the Geneva Convention, and that
Common Article 3 says that, you know, there will be no outrages upon human
dignity. That’s like
—
it’s very vague. What does that mean, ‘outrages upon human (recte
personal) dignity’? That's a statement that is wide open to interpretation”.
(http://www.whitehouse.gov/news/releases/2006/09/20060915-2.html)
The capstone moment of Bush’s advocacy of torture came on March 9, 2008,
when the President of the United States vetoed a bill that would have
forbidden the use of torture.
[143] Waldron,
‘Torture and Positive Law’ 1688-1695 discusses these two texts and others.
[144] In
a BBC radio 4 broadcast on February 12, 2008 Justice Antonin Scalia defended
the use of torture. “I suppose it’s the same thing about so-called torture.
Is it really so easy to determine that smacking someone in the face to
determine where he has hidden the bomb that is about to blow up Los Angeles
is prohibited in the constitution?”
...
“It would be absurd to say you couldn’t do that. And once you acknowledge
that, we're into a different game”.
...
“How close does the threat have to be? And how severe can the
infliction of pain be?” At a conference in Ottawa, Canada, Scalia reportedly
used Jack Bauer as a model for employing torture to prevent the “ticking
bomb scenario,” according to an article in the
Toronto Globe and Mail of June 16, 2007.